Nick Bostrom
Rebecca Roache
[Published in New Waves in Applied Ethics, eds. Jesper Ryberg, Thomas Petersen
& Clark Wolf (Pelgrave Macmillan, 2008): pp. 120-152]
Human
enhancement has emerged in recent years as a blossoming topic in applied
ethics. With continuing advances in science and technology, people are
beginning to realize that some of the basic parameters of the human condition
might be changed in the future. One important way in which the human condition
could be changed is through the enhancement of basic human capacities. If this
becomes feasible within the lifespan of many people alive today, then it is
important now to consider the normative questions raised by such prospects. The
answers to these questions might not only help us be better prepared when
technology catches up with imagination, but they may be relevant to many
decisions we make today, such as decisions about how much funding to give to
various kinds of research.
Enhancement is typically contraposed
to therapy. In broad terms, therapy aims to fix something that has gone wrong,
by curing specific diseases or injuries, while enhancement interventions aim to
improve the state of an organism beyond its normal healthy state. However, the
distinction between therapy and enhancement is problematic, for several reasons.
First, we may note that the
therapy-enhancement dichotomy does not map onto any corresponding dichotomy
between standard-contemporary-medicine and
medicine-as-it-could-be-practised-in-the-future. Standard contemporary medicine
includes many practices that do not aim to cure diseases or injuries. It
includes, for example, preventive medicine, palliative care, obstetrics, sports
medicine, plastic surgery, contraceptive devices, fertility treatments,
cosmetic dental procedures, and much else. At the same time, many enhancement
interventions occur outside of the medical framework. Office workers enhance
their performance by drinking coffee. Make-up and grooming are used to enhance
appearance. Exercise, meditation, fish oil, and
Second, it is unclear how to
classify interventions that reduce the probability of disease and death.
Vaccination can be seen as an immune system enhancement or, alternatively, as a
preventative therapeutic intervention. Similarly, an intervention to slow the
aging process could be regarded either as an enhancement of healthspan or as a
preventative therapeutic intervention that reduces the risk of illness and
disability.
Third, there is the question of how
to define a normal healthy state. Many human attributes have a normal (bell
curve) distribution. Take cognitive capacity. To define abnormality as falling
(say) two standard deviations below the population average is to introduce an
arbitrary point that seems to lack any fundamental medical or normative
significance. One person might have a recognizable neurological disease that
reduces her cognitive capacity by one standard deviation (1σ), yet she would
remain above average if she started off 2σ above the average. A
therapeutic intervention that cured her of her disease might cause her
intelligence to soar further above the average. We might say that for her, a normal healthy state is 2σ
above the average, while for most humans the healthy state is much lower. In
contrast, for somebody whose “natural” cognitive capacity is 2σ below the
average, an intervention that increased it so that she reached a point merely
1σ below the average would be an enhancement. As a result, an enhanced
person may end up with lower capacity than even an unenhanced person with
subnormal cognitive functioning; and therapeutic treatment may turn a merely
gifted person into a genius. In cases like these, it is hard to see what
ethical significance attaches to the classification of an intervention as therapeutic
or enhancing. Moreover, in many cases it is unclear that there is a fact of the
matter as to whether the complex set of factors determining a person’s
cognitive capacity is pathological or normal. Does having a gene present in 20%
of the population that correlates negatively with intelligence constitute a
pathology? Having a large number of such genes might make an individual cognitively
impaired or even retarded, but not necessarily through any distinctive
pathological process. The concepts of “disease” or “abnormality” may not refer
to any natural kind in this context. These concepts are arguably not useful
ways of characterizing a constellation of factors that are normally distributed
in a population, as are many of the factors influencing cognitive capacity or
other candidate targets for enhancement. A concept that defined enhancement as
an improvement achieved otherwise than by curing specific disease or injury
would inherit these problems of defining pathology.
Fourth, capacities vary continuously
not only within a population but also within the lifespan of a single
individual. When we mature, our physical and mental capacities increase; as we
grow old, they decline. If an intervention enables an 80-year-old person to
have the same physical stamina, visual acuity, and reaction time as he had in
his twenties, does that constitute therapy or enhancement? Either alternative
seems as plausible or natural as the other, suggesting again that the concept
of enhancement fails to pick out, in any clear or useful way, a scientifically
significant category.
Fifth, we may wonder how “internal”
an intervention has to be in order to count as an enhancement (or a therapy).
Lasik surgery is a therapy for poor vision. What about contact lenses? Glasses?
Computer software that presents text in an enlarged font? A personal assistant who
handles all the paperwork? Without some requirement that an intervention be
“internal”, all technologies and
tools would constitute enhancements in that they give us capacities to achieve certain
outcomes more easily or effectively than we could otherwise do. If we insist on
an internality constraint, as we must if the concept of enhancement is not to
collapse into the concept of technology generally, then we face the problem of
how to define such a constraint. If we believe that enhancements raise any
special ethical issues, we also face the challenge of showing why the
particular way we have defined the internality constraint captures anything of
normative significance.
Sixth, even if we could define a
concept of enhancement that captured some sort of unified phenomenon in the
world, there is the problem of justifying the claim that the moral status of enhancements
is different from that of other kinds of interventions that modify or increase
human capacities to the same effect.
Defining the therapy-enhancement
distinction is a problem only for those who maintain that this distinction has
practical or normative significance. Those who hold that therapy is
permissible, or worthy of support, or an appropriate target for public funding,
but that enhancement is not, are affected by all the difficulties mentioned
above. We can call subscribers to this anti-enhancement view bioconservatives. Transhumanists (advocates of human enhancement) are unaffected by
the problems associated with maintaining that there are important differences
between enhancement and therapy. Transhumanists hold that we should seek to
develop and make available human enhancement options in the same way and for
the same reasons that we try to develop and make available options for
therapeutic medical treatments: in order to protect and expand life, health,
cognition, emotional well-being, and other states or attributes that
individuals may desire in order to improve their lives.
In
the following five sections, we briefly consider several particular areas of
potential human enhancement: life extension, physical enhancement, enhancement
of mood or personality, cognitive enhancement, and pre- and perinatal
interventions. Our aim is not to give an exhaustive assessment of these types
of enhancement; rather, by considering one or two key issues for each type, we hope
to provide some insight into why they have become topics of ethical debate in
recent years, and some understanding of a few key ethical concerns surrounding
enhancement.
Human life expectancy in the Stone
Age, and for present-day native “non-civilized” populations, is estimated at
around 20-34 years. We might regard this as the natural life expectancy at
birth for our species. Among those who survive infancy and childhood to reach
the age of 15, life expectancy is about 54[1].
In recent times,
To make further radical gains in human life
expectancy, it will become necessary to slow or reverse aspects of human aging.
If the processes of senescence are left unchecked, then there comes a point in
each individual’s life where cellular damage accumulates to such a degree that
pathology and death become inevitable. Preventing and curing specific diseases
can only have a limited impact on life expectancy in a population that already
lives as long as people do in the industrialized world. If we cured all heart disease, life expectancy in
the
There is another reason why life extension
enthusiasts particularly favour research into anti-aging and rejuvenation
medicine. It is that a successful retardation of senescence would extend
healthspan, not just lifespan. In other words, retarding senescence would
enable us to grow older without aging. Instead of seeing our health peak within
the first few decades of life before gradually declining, we could remain at
our fittest and healthiest indefinitely. For many, this represents a wonderful
opportunity to experience, learn, and achieve many things that are simply not
possible given current human life expectancy.
Others, however, believe that dramatically
increasing lifespan would deprive life of meaning and exacerbate the existing
social problems associated with an aging population. These perceived drawbacks
have been cited by bioconservatives like Leon Kass as reasons not to pursue
life extension enhancement[5].
Let us consider whether this view is justified.
Bernard Williams, despite conceding that death
is an evil and therefore an appropriate object of fear, held that an immortal
life free from the prospect of death would be meaningless[6].
An immortal life, on his view, would be worse than a finite one because those
projects that give one’s life meaning and mark out one’s life as one’s own
would eventually be completed or abandoned, leaving infinite years of life in
which there are no remaining ambitions or desires to fulfil. Of course, one
could create new projects and ambitions to replace the old; but in this case it
is not clear that the pursuer of the new projects is, in the ordinary sense,
the same person as the pursuer of the
old ones: what we would end up with would not be a single, cohesive life but a
series of separate but overlapping lives. Williams takes considerations like
these to provide prima facie plausible
reasons for opposing radical life extension[7].
Transhumanists can respond to these
considerations in at least two ways. First, those who oppose radical life
extension on the ground that an immortal or very long-lived life is not
worthwhile may advocate abandoning research into life-extension technology, and
may even advocate preventing people from using it once it becomes available. However,
the question of whether an extremely long-lived life would be worth living is not
obviously relevant to the question of whether a life is worth saving[8],
and that there may be reasons to
consider a certain type of life not worthwhile does not in itself justify
preventing those who wish to live such a life from doing so. There are plenty
of lifestyles led by people today that many might consider not worthwhile; for
example, lifestyles entirely devoted to apparently worthless pursuits such as
playing computer games or watching daytime TV, or lifestyles devoid of
intellectual, social, or cultural enrichment. However, our having this belief about
them is not sufficient reason for preventing those who live them from going on
living them—by, for example, restricting access to life-saving medicine. Providing
they are not significantly harming others, people who live in a liberal,
democratic society are free to pursue whatever lifestyle they choose. That
there may be reasons to believe that an extremely long-lived life would not be
worthwhile, then, does not in itself justify preventing those who wish
radically to extend their lifespan from doing so, if the means of doing so and
the resulting extended life do not significantly harm others.
Second, whilst Williams’ claim that our lives
derive meaning and a sense of cohesion from the projects that we pursue during
our lifetimes is plausible, his argument does not support the conclusion that
no immortal or extremely long life would be worth living. In devising the sort
of projects that lend meaning and a sense of cohesion to our lives, we
presuppose that we will live for a certain number of years; say, until we are
eighty. Projects and ambitions such as mastering a musical instrument, learning
a foreign language, meeting one’s grandchildren, sailing around the world, and
building one’s own house all set challenges that can realistically be achieved
within a lifetime. Projects and ambitions like mastering every musical
instrument in the orchestra, writing a book in each of all the major languages,
planting a new garden and seeing it mature, teaching one’s
great-great-grandchildren how to fish, travelling to Alpha Centauri, or just
seeing history unfold over a few hundred years are not realistic: there is
simply not enough time to achieve them given current life expectancy. If, like
Elina Makropulos in the Karel Čapek play from whose English translation
Williams’ paper takes its name, one were to live for forty-two years fully
expecting to die in a few decades’ time and then take the elixir of life and
look forward to infinite existence, one could expect one’s projects eventually
to expire, leaving one with a choice between eternal boredom and
self-reinvention. (Elina eventually chooses to stop taking the elixir, and dies.)
But this is because these projects reflect a belief about when one is likely to
die. If we could reasonably expect from an early age to live indefinitely, we
could embark on projects designed to keep us occupied for hundreds or thousands
of years. Such projects could lend to the radically extended life the sort of
cohesion that more ephemeral projects lend to current lives. Indefinite life
extension, far from burdening people with a choice between boredom and a
disjointed existence, could represent a great opportunity for those willing to
embrace this new way of thinking about their lives and what they can reasonably
hope to achieve within them.
A more practical objection to radical life
extension is that keeping people alive indefinitely would lead to overpopulation,
and that more old people would place an unacceptable financial burden on the
young.
Let us address the latter part of this objection
first. One response is that, whilst the idea of extending lifespan by directly addressing
the mechanism that causes us to age may be fairly novel, attempts to prolong
life are all around us. Medicine, seatbelts in cars, health warnings on
cigarettes, and the fluorescent jackets that roadside labourers wear are all designed
to prolong the life of those who use them. If prolonging life is to be
discouraged, we should not only forego enhancement, but also rethink the way we
live and commit to less cautious lifestyles.
Moreover, tackling the aging
mechanism may actually alleviate many of the problems that we currently associate
with an aging population: many aged people alive today, being too infirm to
work, are reliant on state support, and so the years that modern medicine has
bought them are ones in which their economic contribution to society is
negative. Life extension by delaying or reversing the aging process, in
contrast, would increase healthspan, enabling old people to contribute
financially and otherwise to society well beyond the sixty-five or so years
currently expected. And, when they do finally become ill and die, there is
little reason to think that the cost of their care would be any more expensive
than it is today. In fact, society could benefit from being able to amortise
such costs over a greater number of years[9].
That radical life extension could lead to overpopulation
has its roots in two separate worries: that overpopulation would result from existing
people living longer, and that overpopulation would result from longer-lived
people having more children than people today. Regarding the first worry, we
can note that population growth has slowed over the past fifty years, with less
developed countries accounting for 99% of current growth[10].
Researchers have found that, in general, increasing the standard of living and
education of people living in poverty leads to a decrease in birth rate. Working
to improve the lives of the millions living in poverty worldwide would,
therefore, be a far more effective and humane means of tackling the issue of
overpopulation than impeding efforts to develop life extension technology—especially
when we consider that this technology is likely to be available first in
developed countries, many of which are seeing their population decline.
In response to the worry that longer-lived
people will have more children, increasing lifespan would not increase the
number of people being born unless there is also an increase in the number of
years in which people—particularly women—can reproduce. If this happened,
however, it is unclear whether the net effect would be to increase the size of the
population. Since 1990, the number of US women under 30 to give birth to their
first child has been declining, with birth rates increasing for those over 30[11].
The average age of first-time mothers is at an all-time high. There is,
therefore, a trend of postponing childbirth until later in life; a trend
particularly evident among well-educated women, who choose to develop their
careers before starting a family. However, since women’s fertility begins to
decrease after the age of 35, there is a pressure on women to have children
before it is too late, and so there is a limit to how long childbirth can be
postponed. Were it possible to widen the window of years in which women could
conceive, this limit would be increased, and so we could expect the current trend
of postponing childbirth to continue beyond the age at which fertility
currently decreases for women. This might result in a reduction in the number
of births per year. Along with the fact that, with enhanced people living
longer, there would also be fewer deaths per year, the net effect of radical
life extension on population size is far from obvious.
Whilst these considerations help to mitigate
the worry that life-extension technology will inevitably lead to an
overpopulated planet, it is difficult to foresee how life-extension might
affect population in the long term. Even if we accept that increasing lifespan
could lead to problems of overpopulation in the future, however, there are more
humane ways of solving the problem than withholding life-saving medical
treatments. We could, for example, consider a policy in which those who want to
avail themselves of radical life-extension would have to agree to limit the
rate at which they bring new people into the world.
We conclude that the arguments we have
considered do not succeed in showing that radical life extension would cause any
insuperable social problems, nor—as Williams believed—that it would reduce the
quality of life of those who make use of it. Biogerontological research can
help us prevent the diseases associated with old age, thereby increasing
quality of life for everyone as our lives advance. The economist William
Nordhaus has estimated that improvements in health status, and especially
increased longevity, have made as large a contribution to the average standard
of living in the
There are
various ways in which we can currently improve what we might call bodily
capacities, which include stamina, strength, dexterity, flexibility,
coordination, agility, and conditioning. We can exercise, eat healthily, take
dietary supplements, avoid pollution, and visit physiotherapists, massage
therapists, and personal trainers.
For many, especially those who enjoy
participating in sports, pursuing activities that improve bodily capacities is
enjoyable, and therefore worthwhile for its own sake. For others, pursuing such
activities is a time-consuming burden reluctantly undertaken as a means to achieve
certain ends, such as maintaining a minimal level of health and fitness and
attempting to delay the physical deterioration associated with aging. For an
unfortunate few who are struggling to recover from a serious injury or illness,
improving bodily capacities can be a difficult and painful feat that must be
accomplished slowly and with the help and support of others. Especially for the
latter two groups of people, the availability of medical interventions that
could improve bodily capacities safely and conveniently would be beneficial. Increasing
one’s strength by taking a drug, for example, would dispense with the need to
spend hours working out at the gym or exercising with a physiotherapist, freeing
up time for other activities.
Those who fall into the first group mentioned,
who enjoy physical activity for its own sake, could also benefit from such
interventions, since improving one’s bodily capacities could enhance one’s
enjoyment of partaking in sports. However, the issue of performance enhancement
in professional sport, or “doping”, is controversial. In fact, it is probably
the most widely-publicised area of enhancement. In this section we shall consider
some of the ethical issues raised by sports enhancement, and assess their
relevance to physical enhancement generally.
The Canadian sprinter, Ben Johnson,
was stripped of an Olympic gold medal following his disqualification for
steroid use. Today, athletes are regularly tested for banned substances, with the
chairman of the World Anti-Doping Agency (WADA) pledging to “level the playing
field and protect the spirit of sport”[13].
Despite the fact that athletes found guilty of
doping are condemned as cheats and punished, however, the feats that drugs
enable them to achieve are sometimes impressive. The journalist David Owen wrote
I have a guilty secret. I think Ben Johnson’s “victory” in the men’s 100m at the 1988 Seoul Olympics is just about the most exciting 10 seconds of sport I have ever witnessed. … [W]hat stood out for me mainly was the sheer bullocking power of Johnson’s sprinting.[14]
Owen’s comments demonstrate that—for some—physical
excellence can be impressive even when achieved with the help of drugs. It is therefore
not surprising that some call for performance-enhancing drugs in sport to be permitted.
Doing so would remove the problem of unfairness: allowing everyone the option
of enhancing would be one way of creating the level playing field sought by
WADA, thereby removing one of the main concerns about illicit doping[15].
Admittedly, this is not the method of levelling that WADA has in mind, but it
is arguably a more effective method than weeding out drug users.
What about the concern expressed by
WADA to “protect the spirit of sport”? WADA states that “[t]he spirit of sport
is the celebration of the human spirit, the body and the mind”[16].
Julian Savulescu et. al. observe that, in ancient times,
sport was about finding “the strongest, fastest, or most skilled man”[17]:
sporting contests were a test of competitors’ strength, speed, and skill. Like
horse and dog racing today, sport in ancient times was “a test of biological
potential”. If this is what the spirit of sport is about, then performance-enhancing
drugs certainly go against it, since athletes can achieve things with the aid
of drugs that they would be unable to achieve based on their natural potential
alone. However, Savulescu et. al.
argue that this is not what sport today is about:
Humans are not horses or dogs. We make choices and exercise our own judgment. We choose what kind of training to use and how to run our race. We can display courage, determination, and wisdom. We are not flogged by a jockey on our back but drive ourselves. It is this judgment that competitors exercise when they choose diet, training, and whether to take drugs. We can choose what kind of competitor to be, not just through training, but through biological manipulation. … Far from being against the spirit of sport, biological manipulation embodies the human spirit—the capacity to improve ourselves on the basis of reason and judgment.[18]
Since, on their view, drugs do not compromise
the spirit of sport, Savulescu et. al.
argue that rather than focus on banning drugs that enhance performance, sporting
authorities should focus on banning drugs that are unsafe, thus ensuring that
professional sport is fair and acceptably safe for all.
Whilst human sports competitors can undoubtedly
prepare for their contests using methods that are not available to horses or
dogs, the biological constitution of competitors nevertheless plays a more
central role in sport than Savulescu et.
al. attribute to it. Sporting contests pit competitors against others
judged to be biologically similar in ways considered relevant to the nature of
the competition: female adults compete in sprinting races against other female
adults but not against males or children, football teams are made up of adults
of the same sex and compete against similar teams, and boxers compete against
those of the same sex who fall into the same weight category. Why is this?
One answer is that the impressiveness of a
sporting feat is relative to the expected biological potential of the
competitor. Running 200 metres in under nineteen seconds is more impressive if
it is accomplished by a man than by a cheetah because it is a more difficult
feat for a man, given the typical biological constitution of men; and lifting
150 kilograms is more impressive if it is done by a female weightlifter than by
a male weightlifter because such a feat is more difficult for a woman than for
a man given their respective typical biological constitutions. In order for us
effectively to compare competitors’ performance in a sporting contest, then,
they need to be drawn from a single biological category[19].
Permitting the use of performance-enhancing
drugs in sport would not necessarily undermine this practice of relativizing
sporting achievements to biological categories. For example, permitting the use
of a drug that enabled all competitors to improve their performance by 10% would
not—if all competitors used such a drug—change the fact that men can generally
lift heavier weights than women, or that adults can run faster than children. Nor
would it by itself enable the second-best competitors to beat the best
competitors. In addition, the use of such a drug would be compatible with the
ancient ideal of using sport to identify “the strongest, fastest, or most
skilled” competitor; it would simply be the case that the competitor in
question is 10% stronger, faster, or more skilled than they would be without
the use of the drug.
Whether we think that such enhancement would
undermine sport depends upon exactly what role the expected biological
potential of competitors plays in our evaluation of their achievements. If we
are interested in testing the unenhanced biological potential of competitors,
the use of drugs would indeed undermine sporting contests, though in this case
we face the problem of explaining why drugs are relevantly different from
other, permitted, means of improving performance, such as special training
regimes and diet plans. If we are simply interested in revealing
differentials—in finding the best, and in assessing competitors’ performance
relative to others—then a drug that gave all competitors a similar advantage
would not undermine this quest. In this case, however, it is difficult to see
what motivation there would be for sporting authorities to permit such
enhancements, since the same differentials would exist whether or not the enhancement
was used[20]. If,
on the other hand, we are interested in seeing how fast, strong, or skilful we
can make humans using whatever means become available, then we should actively
promote performance-enhancing drugs, and expect to see competitors striving to
become the first to discover the latest enhancements in order to beat their
rivals.
For individual elite athletes, of course, the
biggest motivation is likely none of these three; it is to win. Performance-enhancing
drugs appeal to competitors for the same reason that the latest training
regimes, psychological techniques, and clothing appeal to them: they hope to
gain an edge over their competitors. We might say, then, that
performance-enhancing drugs are attractive chiefly because they confer positional goods: goods whose value to
those who have them depends upon others not having them. Many who oppose
enhancement in sport, such as Michael Sandel, worry that permitting it would
lead to an “arms race”, in which competitors who refuse to enhance, or who
cannot afford to do so, are left behind while those with the willingness and
money to enhance strive to be the first to find new and improved drugs[21].
This would allow money, medical support staff, a physique that takes well to
high doses of certain drugs, and a willingness to sacrifice long-term health to
play a far more central role in professional sport than many would wish.
Whether performance-enhancing drugs should be
permitted in sport ultimately depends upon what one believes to be
fundamentally valuable in sport. We will not attempt to argue here for any
particular conception of sport, and so we will remain agnostic about the issue
of whether performance-enhancing drugs should be permitted in sport. In practice,
of course, a decision to ban a particular substance in a sport would also have
to take into account factors such as enforcement costs, the health effects of
the drug, spectator interest, whether one might instead create two versions of
the sport—one where enhancement is allowed and one where it is banned—and other
complicating considerations.
It is important to note, however, that even if
it turns out that physical enhancement would be a bad thing for professional
sport, it may be a good thing for people in other contexts. Many tools and
techniques that we find useful or indispensable in everyday life are banned from
sport. Bicycles are useful even though they are banned from sprinting races. Similarly,
whilst athletes are prohibited from using drugs to make them faster or
stronger, improving our bodily capacities may be desirable outside the sporting
arena.
The concept of positional goods can help
illuminate other applications of enhancement. Generally speaking, the greater
the extent to which some good is positional, the less reason there is for
society to promote that good. Sports enhancements are at an extreme end where
the benefits are almost purely positional. Height enhancements and cosmetic
enhancements may similarly have mostly positional benefits. A taller man may
gain certain social advantages from his impressive stature, but if everybody
become three inches taller nobody is better off than before. Collectively, the
money spent and the risks taken to effect such a change would produce no net
good. This situation contrasts with some other types of enhancement. For
example, health and intelligence have a positional good aspect: being healthy
and smart enables a person to compete more effectively for high-status jobs and
desirable mates. But health and intelligence also have important benefits aside
from these competitive advantages. If we all became a little healthier or a
little smarter, there would be a net benefit: we would suffer less illness and
incapacity and we would be able to understand more of the world.
In practice, the benefits of many physical
enhancements (except ones related to health and longevity) seem to have a very
large positional component. A manual labourer might gain an important
non-positional benefit from an enhancement that increases strength and stamina;
but the value of such enhancement outside the sporting and cosmetic arenas is
questionable. Typically, the most effective means of achieving super-human
strength and stamina are through the use of “external” tools rather than
physical enhancements: we increase our ability to perform hard physical jobs
through the use of forklifts and jackhammers rather than anabolic steroids.
In Listening To Prozac, the psychiatrist
Peter Kramer describes how some of his patients who had completed a course of
Prozac to relieve their depression wished to resume taking it. This was not
because their depression had returned: medically speaking, they were no longer
mentally ill. Rather, whilst taking Prozac, the patients had felt “better than
well”[22].
Prozac, as well as relieving their medical condition, had—in their view—improved
various aspects of their personality which had never been classed as part of
their illness: shy patients had become more outgoing and assertive, compulsive
patients had become more relaxed and easy-going, and those with low self-esteem
had become more confident. Is there anything wrong with prescribing a drug like
Prozac for someone who is not suffering from any medically-recognized
condition, but who simply wants to improve their mood or personality?
One difficulty complicating this area of enhancement
is that in many cases it is not clear what would count as an improvement of
mood or personality. We might think that those who are so shy that their
choices in life are severely limited by the fact that they find simple social
interactions highly distressing, or those who are so aggressive that they
regularly come into violent conflict with others, ought to be offered
personality-enhancing drugs if, on balance, these might improve their lives. However,
traits like shyness and aggression are manifested in people to varying degrees,
with correspondingly various effects on the way the person in question lives
their life. The extent to which an intervention that, say, enabled someone who
feels mild unease in unfamiliar social situations to become the life and soul
of the party is an improvement or the reverse is difficult to assess, since
there is no obvious sense in which a shy person is “better” than a confident
one, or vice versa. This difficulty is compounded by the possibility that what
the subject views—qua subject—as an
improvement may not coincide with what those who interact with him judge to be
an improvement: the sort of intervention described above may make the subject
feel more confident and comfortable in certain situations, but others may find
the resulting person less pleasant to interact with. (Alcohol can have the
effect of making shy people more confident, yet most sober people interact with
other sober people in preference to people in possession of Dutch courage.) Also
complicating assessments about what counts as an improvement is the distinction
between improvements in some particular dimension (happiness, confidence, and
so on) and improvements in life generally. It is, other things equal,
preferable to experience states like happiness, satisfaction, and love than
states like sadness, frustration, and grief; yet experiencing undesirable
states can improve our understanding of ourselves and others, and give our
personalities a richness and depth that they might lack were we only ever to
experience “positive” emotions.
In order to decide what changes in a person’s
mood or personality count as improvements, then, we must confront questions
like: By what standard do we assess improvements or the reverse in cases where
a person’s mood or personality does not have a seriously adverse effect on
their life? Is it even plausible to claim that there could be such a standard? If
so, what is the best guide to what the standard is and how it applies in a
particular case: the opinion of the subject, the opinions of those who interact
with the subject, or something else? The importance of addressing such
questions does not entail that mood and personality enhancement is impossible
or inadvisable; but a certain amount of philosophical reflection and analysis
is required if we are to gain genuine benefits from such technology. This need
for philosophical reflection is not unique to questions relating to
enhancement, but pervades everyday life. When making decisions like whether to
change careers, end a long-term personal relationship, or have another cream
cake, we must at least implicitly ask ourselves questions about how our
decision will affect our lives, whether the benefits it brings are of the right
sort given our ambitions and goals, and whether we can do without the benefits
and opportunities that our decision would close off to us.
Despite these difficulties, there are many
changes in mood or personality that seem, quite straightforwardly, to be
improvements. Listening to a piece of inspiring music, discovering that one has
an hour longer than expected in bed before the alarm sounds, and eating an
excellent dinner can all lift one’s spirits. An unexpected act of kindness from
a stranger can lead one to resolve to be more considerate to others. Or, one
may spontaneously decide to forgive an old adversary and unburden oneself of
long-held anger and resentment. Most would agree that such changes are
improvements: they are enjoyable to experience, they make us more pleasant for
others to interact with, and they are the sort of changes that, in their small
ways, make one’s life go better. If we could bring about such changes using
drugs, shouldn’t they uncontroversially count as enhancements of mood or
personality?
Even those who agree that such changes are
improvements may object to the use of drugs in order to achieve them. Leon Kass
expresses such a line of thought:
In most of our ordinary efforts at self-improvement, either by practice or training or study, we sense the relation between our doings and the resulting improvement, between the means used and the end sought. There is an experiential and intelligible connection between means and ends; we can see how confronting fearful things might eventually enable us to cope with our fears. We can see how curbing our appetites produces self-command. … In contrast, biomedical interventions act directly on the human body and bring about their effects on a subject who is not merely passive but who plays no role at all. He can at best feel their effects without understanding their meaning in human terms.[23]
By improving oneself using drugs, then, one
foregoes a valuable aspect of improving oneself via more conventional means. Is
this a good reason to forego enhancement?
Well, even if we concede that certain means of
achieving an improvement can add value to the end state, the end state may have
value independently of the means by which it is achieved, meaning that bringing
about the end state using less valuable means is better than not bringing it
about at all. To use one of Kass’s examples, whilst attaining an increased
level of self-command may gain additional value if it is brought about by
curbing one’s appetites, the end state—a mastery of self-command—has value even
if it is brought about using drugs. Moreover, we do not generally feel
ourselves obliged always to wring as much value as possible from the process of
achieving a valuable end state: we may catch a bus to get somewhere even though
we recognise that there is additional value to be gained from jogging instead,
or we may employ a gardener to cultivate a garden even though we recognise that
there is additional value to be gained from doing it ourselves. Since, in
general, we are often content to achieve a valuable end state without using the
most value-adding means, additional argument is required to support the claim
that the practice of improving our capacities using drugs should be subject to
different standards.
One important complex of questions about the
use of pharmaceutical means to influence mood and personality concerns the idea
of authenticity. Kramer spent a large fraction of his book struggling with the
reports of some of his patients, who claimed that Prozac had helped them to
find their “true self”, enabling them to be the person they really were. They
identified with their on-drug persona and viewed their earlier “natural” state
as a long-lasting aberration, an alien condition that they had never been able
to escape. It seems possible that in some cases the use of drugs can help a
person live more authentically. At
the same time, however, we can conceive of cases in which drug-induced emotions
would undermine authenticity. Sometimes it seems important that our emotions
respond to life events in appropriate ways. We may want to be the kind of
person who would feel deep sadness at the loss of a loved one; and if the loss
should occur, we may want to experience grief. A person who used pills to
disconnect her emotional life completely from what happened to her and to the
people she cared about could plausibly be said to have disabled a very
important part of her humanity.
Mood and personality enhancement technology,
then, has the potential to make a considerable positive impact on our lives;
but it is important that those who intend to make use of such technology engage
with the difficult philosophical questions that surround it.
There are
many ways in which we try to enhance our cognitive capacities; that is, those
capacities that we use for gaining, processing, storing, and retrieving information.
Language, education, mastery of psychological techniques, drinking coffee or
energy drinks, meditation, exercise, sleep, and taking herbal or vitamin
supplements can all play a part in improving various aspects of our cognitive performance.
Moreover, none of these methods of enhancement is controversial, and
some—notably the acquisition of language, and education—are considered so
central to living even a minimally successful life that to deny our children
adequate access to them would be deemed seriously negligent.
In addition to these familiar methods, a number
of novel possibilities for cognitive enhancement have emerged in recent years[24].
For example, Modafinil, a drug originally used to treat narcolepsy, has
memory-enhancing as well as alertness-enhancing effects[25].
Ritalin, developed to treat attention-deficit hyperactivity disorder, can
improve concentration in healthy adults[26].
Transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) may improve some forms of motor
learning[27]. Variations
in some genes in humans have been shown to account for up to 5% of memory
performance[28],
raising the possibility of cognition-enhancing genetic interventions in the
future. Supplementation of a mother’s diet during late pregnancy and three
months post-partum with long-chained fatty acids has been shown to improve
cognitive performance in children[29].
Given the diverse means by which we try to improve our cognitive performance for
various purposes today, we can expect many to be excited by the opportunities
that such novel technologies offer to improve our lives in ways previously
unavailable to us. What ethical issues surround the possibility of cognitive
enhancement?
Many ethical issues are familiar from our
discussion of other types of enhancement. For example, enhanced intelligence,
attention, and so on are – to some extent – positional goods, since they give
the enhanced an advantage over others when competing for such things as places
at university and certain types of job. In this respect, cognitive enhancement
raises the same concerns about “arms races” as physical enhancement; and the
ways of addressing these concerns are similar to those discussed earlier. However,
improvements in cognitive capacities could have instrumental and intrinsic value
that is far greater than that of improved physical capacities. Being able to
think better would equip us to solve important political and social problems,
make scientific breakthroughs, and so on; and various studies indicate that
more intelligent people earn more[30],
are less likely to suffer a range of social and economic misfortunes[31],
and are healthier[32].
Moreover, being able to understand other people, appreciate great literature,
make plans, be creative, and remember one’s own past are non-instrumentally
important for human flourishing.
Also familiar from our discussion of physical
enhancement is the question of whether using such enhancement in certain
contexts constitutes cheating. Just as using drugs to enhance one’s strength is
seen as cheating in professional sport, using drugs to improve one’s memory in
order to perform better in an examination could be seen as cheating. Analogous
with the case of doping, whether cognitive enhancement is deemed unacceptable in
the context of education depends on what we value about education, and what its
“rules” are. For example, if education is primarily a competition for grades,
then enhancement may be viewed as cheating if some people did not have access
to it, or if its use contravened the rules. If, on the other hand, the value of
education consists in equipping students with skills and knowledge that will
improve their own lives and society generally, then cognitive enhancement could
play an important role in education.
The medical forms of cognitive enhancement that
are immediately on the horizon are likely to yield at best small to moderate
improvements in memory, concentration, mental energy, and some other
cognition-relevant attributes. We can speculate about radical improvements in
cognitive ability that might become possible in the more distant future. Such
extreme enhancements would raise some unique ethical issues that do not arise
in the same way for other human enhancements. In particular, people with
radically enhanced cognitive capacities might gain vast advantages in terms of
income, strategic planning, and the ability to influence others; in other
words, an enhanced cognitive elite may gain socially significant amounts of
power.
This raises the worry, described by the
geneticist Lee Silver[33],
that the enhanced, having gained cognitive abilities that far outstrip those of
the unenhanced, could band together and use their superior skills to dominate
and exploit the unenhanced. If the cognitive enhancements in question were
brought about through germline genetic intervention, the resulting improvements
could be inherited by the children of the enhanced, with successive
improvements eventually resulting in the enhanced forming a new species which
may prove a threat to unenhanced humans.
That enhancement might result in such a
two-tier society may be rather far-fetched, however. First, biomedical
cognitive enhancements tend to have the greatest benefits for those who start
from a low level of cognitive functioning[34].
Intuitively this is unsurprising, since it is usually easier to correct some
specific deficit that is impeding a brain’s performance than to take a
well-calibrated, highly-efficient neural system and boost its performance still
further. As a result, far from being socially divisive, cognitive enhancement
could potentially increase equality in society by enabling those with lower
cognitive ability to function at a level that is closer to those with naturally
high cognitive ability. Second, if people are free to pick and choose which
enhancements they undergo, it is highly unlikely that society will split
cleanly into two disjoint groups, the enhanced and the unenhanced. More likely,
society will consist of a continuum of differently modified people, ranging
from the unenhanced, through those who have undergone a small amount of
enhancement, to those who have undergone major enhancement. This new spectrum
of differences would be superimposed on the existing range of native
capacities, educations, experiences, privileges, and unique situational
advantages that already causes people to display widely varying cognitive
skills. Third, we already live in a society that contains diverse groups of
people who could potentially come into conflict, but often do not: short people
and tall ones, males and females, healthy and sick, educated and uneducated,
and so on. The existence of diverse groups in a well-functioning society does
not entail that those who make up one side of the division have cause to unite
and oppose everyone else. On the contrary, many believe that diversity in society
can be enriching for all[35].
Another worry is that the possibilities offered
by cognitive enhancement might lead us to view those people with below-average
cognitive ability as diseased, rather than as part of the normal human spectrum
of abilities. In 2003, the Nobel Prize-winning biologist, James Watson, caused
controversy when he suggested in a television documentary that there might come
a time when we can “cure” stupidity:
If you really are stupid, I would call that a disease. The lower ten percent who really have difficulty, even in elementary school, what’s the cause of it? A lot of people would like to say, “Well, poverty, things like that.” It probably isn’t. So I’d like to get rid of that, to help the lower ten percent.[36]
Whilst abrasively formulated, Watson’s claim raises
some important issues about the treatment of people of very low intelligence. For
example, whilst Watson’s “lower ten percent” may have most to gain from
cognitive enhancement—in that improved cognitive functioning could better equip
them to participate fully in modern society—they may also be less likely than
more intelligent, better informed people to pursue the possibilities that
enhancement could offer them; unless, perhaps, the possibility of such
enhancement is suggested to them by a doctor. This is much more likely to
happen if their low intelligence is recognised as a medical disorder. In
addition, included in this group of people will be those whose cognitive
functioning falls so far below the average that society deems them incapable of
making certain important life decisions—such as where to live and what to do
with their lives—which must instead be delegated to a carer. Cognitive
enhancement could enable these people to gain autonomy over their own lives;
however, given their impaired cognitive abilities, it is probable that they
would be deemed incapable of consenting to receive enhancing treatment. Is it
right that they should be forced to forego treatment that could give them the
sort of independence that the majority of us enjoy?
That enhancing treatment should be withheld
from severely cognitively-impaired people might be seen as a consequence of our
current way of thinking about medicine. According to this way of thinking, it is
acceptable to treat a severely cognitively-impaired person for conditions
recognised as diseases or injuries, such as cancer or a broken leg, despite the
fact that he is incapable of giving consent. Generally, we believe that such
treatment is acceptable because it is in the person’s best interests; whereas
leaving him untreated would be contrary to his best interests. On the other
hand, it is not clear that an avoidable enhancement, such as a facelift, would
be in his best interests. Since very low intelligence, like having facial
wrinkles, is not universally recognised as a disease state, it is questionable on
the current medical model whether it serves the best interests of a
cognitively-impaired person to undergo cognitive enhancement treatment.
This medical model, according to which treatment
for disease is seen as necessary whereas enhancement is seen as gratuitous, is
arguably outdated. To begin, we saw earlier that there are many problems
associated with holding that the distinction between therapy and enhancement is
practically or morally significant. In addition to this, it has been argued
that decisions about what would make people’s lives go best—and also,
therefore, what is in their best interests—should be guided not by whether a
treatment will cure a disease or heal an injury, but by whether it will
increase well-being. Savulescu tells us that, “[i]t is not [disease] which is
important. People often trade length of life for non-health related well-being.
Non-disease [states] may prevent us from leading the best life”[37].
On this view, we might conclude that, since it is acceptable to treat diseases
or injuries in those who are unable to give consent, it is also acceptable to treat
non-disease states in such people if the treatment would increase well-being,
provided that the level of well-being we expect them to achieve is not likely
to be outweighed by any stress or risks associated with the treatment. Moving
away from a model that associates medical treatment with disease would enable
cognitively-impaired people to receive enhancing treatment without committing
ourselves to the view that such people are diseased. (It could also give these
people the cognitive capacities needed to make an autonomous decision about whether
they want to retain these capacities or go back to their earlier impaired
state.)
Despite this argument for shifting the focus of
medicine away from the treatment of disease and towards the promotion of
well-being, the current system of licensing medicines exerts a pull in the
opposite direction. This system was created to deal with traditional medicine
which aims to prevent, detect, cure, or mitigate diseases. In this framework,
there is no room for enhancing medicine. For example, drug companies could find
it difficult to get regulatory approval for a pharmaceutical whose sole use is
to improve cognitive functioning in the healthy population. To date, every
pharmaceutical on the market that offers some potential cognitive enhancement
effect was developed to treat some specific disease condition (such as ADHD,
narcolepsy, and Alzheimer’s disease). The enhancing effects of these drugs in
healthy subjects is a serendipitous unintended effect. As a result,
pharmaceutical companies, instead of aiming directly at enhancements for
healthy people, must work indirectly by demonstrating that their drugs are
effective in treating some recognised disease. One perverse effect of this incentive
structure is the medicalization and “pathologization” of conditions that were
previously regarded as part of the normal human spectrum. If a significant
fraction of the population could obtain certain benefits from drugs that
improve concentration, for example, it is currently necessary to categorize
this segment of people as having some disease in order for the drug to be
approved and prescribed to those who could benefit from it. It is not enough
that people would like to be able to concentrate better when they work; they
must be stamped as suffering from attention-deficit hyperactivity disorder: a
condition now estimated to affect between 3 and 5 percent of school-age
children (a higher proportion among boys) in the
In conclusion, whilst cognitive enhancement
offers real benefits, not least to those who currently lack sufficient cognitive
skills to exert autonomy over their own lives, it also highlights aspects of
our current medical model that need to be updated and revised. Doing so in the
way that we have described would help ensure fair and equal access to
enhancement, and would also help speed progress in enhancement technology by
allowing pharmaceutical companies to focus on developing enhancements without
also having to ensure that they can be used to treat a recognised pathogenic
condition.
As well as
helping us to improve our existing capacities, enhancement technology could
also help ensure that future generations are genetically disposed to be
smarter, healthier, and happier than those who have come before.
There are several ways of doing this, many of
which are familiar and accepted. Most obviously, we are free to choose our
sexual partners, which plays a major role in determining the genetic
composition of our children. Pregnant mothers can take folic acid supplements
which, whilst not affecting the genetic composition of the child, can affect
the epigenetic expression of their genes. Young girls receive inoculations
against rubella in order to avoid the risk of later giving birth to a child
with brain damage and other problems associated with congenital rubella
syndrome.
On the other hand, there are some novel and ethically
controversial methods of ensuring that a child will be born with a certain
genetic composition. First, there is pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD). This
is a technique that allows doctors to determine the sex of an embryo and its genetic
disposition to diseases such as cystic fibrosis and haemophilia. Current
More effective in producing embryos with the
right sort of genes would be ensuring that their biological parents have the
appropriate high capacities. Human mating preferences have evolved to
discriminate on the basis of traits that in our environment of evolutionary
adaptation correlated with fitness. While few people are interested in
overriding their natural romantic inclinations in order to achieve some
conscious eugenic purpose, the issue does arise in a more plausible way for
infertile couples who are reliant on donor gametes and who might have the
option of selecting the source of these gametes. This opportunity has been
exploited by eugenicists, without much success, as Sandel tells us:
The Repository for Germinal Choice, one of
Despite
these difficulties, the practice of buying gametes from donors is fairly popular,
most famously in the
Another way of creating children of a certain
genetic quality is to manipulate the genetic material of the embryo to attempt
to ensure the presence or absence of certain traits in the resulting child. This
sort of intervention is novel and risky, and it is currently permitted in the
Is there anything wrong with using any of these
techniques to produce children with desirable qualities? Well, we might worry
that some of these techniques harm the embryos. In the case of PGD, for every
embryo that is selected for implantation, at least one (or, more likely,
several) will be discarded, never to be allowed to develop. For those who
believe that the moral status of embryos is on a par with that of fully
developed humans, this amounts to murder, or at least to letting-die. The moral
status of the embryo is a hotly debated topic in bioethics, and one that we do
not have the space to address here. However, it is worth mentioning that, even
where PGD does not take place, IVF treatment involves discarding embryos. As a
result, those who do not find IVF treatment morally objectionable cannot
consistently raise this objection in relation to PGD. Those who do object to
IVF treatment because it involves discarding embryos should note that over half
of embryos produced by sexual intercourse fail to develop; so those who object
to IVF must (in the absence of an argument to show why the two cases are
relevantly different) also object to unmediated procreation.
The possibility of genetic manipulation of
embryos raises different issues about harm. First, there is a risk that such
manipulation will have unintended effects, resulting in a child who is worse
off than he or she would have been had no such intervention occurred. For this
reason, it may be wise to avoid using this technology until it is advanced
enough for us to be sure that the expected benefits outweigh the risks. Second,
even disregarding such risks, Jürgen Habermas argues that genetic manipulation
infringes the freedom of the resulting child in a way that ordinary parenting
does not. Parents currently exert control over their children via the
communicative, linguistic “medium of reasons”, meaning that “the adolescents in
principle still have the opportunity to respond to and retroactively break away
from it”[44]. On
the other hand,
in the case of a genetic determination carried out according to the parents’ own preferences, there is no such opportunity. With genetic enhancement, there is no communicative scope for the projected child to be addressed as a second person and to be involved in a communication process. From the adolescent’s perspective, an instrumental determination cannot, like a pathogenic socialisation process, be revised by “critical reappraisal.” It does not permit the adolescent looking back on the prenatal intervention to engage in a revisionary learning process.
Because of this, a child whose genetic traits have been selected by his parents is denied the opportunity of being “the undivided author or his own life”[45].
Habermas’s objection to prenatal interventions that do not involve the child in a communicative process, however, also applies to many practices not generally considered controversial and often considered sensible or potentially beneficial, such as taking folic acid supplements, eating healthily, and abstaining from taking drugs during pregnancy. Moreover, it is impossible completely to avoid non-communicative interventions: the environment in which very young children are raised literally shapes their nervous system in ways that they cannot later undo. Language-learning is one such process that cannot be undone; and it is, in addition, a necessary condition for entering the “medium of reasons” that surrounds what Habermas takes to be more acceptable means of controlling children.
Habermas’s concern about autonomy is also misplaced. Genetic factors—along with many other influences—affect what we are able to achieve in life regardless of whether our genes have been specially selected for us. A child whose genes have been specially chosen is, therefore, no less free or autonomous than a child born with whatever genetic constitution happened to result from their conception. On the contrary, a child who, as a result of genetic manipulation, is born with improvements in capacities such as intelligence and general health is likely to enjoy more rather than less autonomy, in the sense that she will be better equipped to realize the plans and ambitions she devises for her life. As a last resort, however, we can note that a child who grows up to resent having had features like increased intelligence and better health selected for her by her parents is free to destroy their effects, for example by ingesting poisons. That it is difficult to conceive of a rational person wanting to do such a thing underlines how implausible it is to maintain that having such selected traits is unconditionally disadvantageous.
Disregarding the issue of harm to the embryo or
the resulting child, some believe that there is something sinister about the
very desire to create people of a certain genetic quality. Sandel, for example,
believes that the desire to “remake nature, including human nature, to serve
our purposes and satisfy our desires” fails to exemplify, “and may even destroy
… an appreciation of the gifted character of human powers and achievements”[46].
In the case of parents who wish to shape the genetic constitution of their
child, Sandel believes that the desire for a child of a certain genetic quality
is incompatible with the special type of love that parents have for their
children. This is because “[t]o appreciate children as gifts is to accept them
as they come, not as objects of our design or products of our will or instruments
of our ambition”[47].
Sandel’s critique of genetic engineering is not
convincing, however. It is far from obvious that genetic engineering would
destroy our appreciation of life or our sense of children as gifts. Sandel
cites no data in support of his claim that parents would love their children
less for failing to “accept them as they come”; and intuitively, as Nick
Bostrom has commented, it seems plausible that “[s]ome mothers and fathers
might find it easier to love a child who, thanks to enhancements, is bright,
beautiful, healthy, and happy”[48].
In addition, we already attempt to influence the features of our children in
many ways that are universally accepted to be compatible with good, loving
parenting. We attempt to improve their literacy skills by encouraging them to
read. We try to develop their team spirit and social skills by encouraging them
to take part in games and sport. We instil discipline and shape their behaviour
by using punishments and rewards. Between Sandel’s extremes of accepting children
as they come and viewing them as objects of our design, then, there is plenty
of room for affecting the sort of people our children will become without
undermining our love for them. Ensuring that children have the genes to help
them do well in life, providing that we do so with their best interests at
heart, plausibly falls within this acceptable middle ground.
That we need to keep the child’s best interests
in mind when selecting traits for him is an important point. On the one hand, people
benefit from being more intelligent, healthier, having good social skills, and
so on. It is plausible to suggest that, if we have the capability to ensure
that our children are genetically disposed to have such traits, then it is
desirable to make use of this capability, since doing so will benefit our
children. Julian Savulescu defends a principle of “procreative beneficence”, which
states that IVF parents-to-be who are offered PGD to screen their multiple embryos
for genetic predispositions to disease and non-disease states are morally
obliged to select that child who can be expected to have the best life. For
example, if they have a choice of implanting one of two embryos which are
genetically identical except in that only one of them is genetically
predisposed to high intelligence, the parents-to-be are morally obliged to
select that embryo over the other, since a more intelligent child is likely to
have a better life than a less intelligent one, other things being equal[49].
When we use PGD to select between embryos, our
choices determine which of several possible persons will come into existence.
By contrast, when we genetically manipulate an embryo, we need not be determining
which person will come into existence; instead our interventions affect what
sort of person this embryo will develop into and what capacities she will have.
This distinction may make an ethical difference. For example, one could hold
that if an embryo with a genetic predisposition to a disability is selected for
implantation, this is permissible because nobody is harmed. The embryo may grow
into a person with a disability, but since this person would not otherwise have
existed, she cannot be said to have been harmed by our action—at least if we
assume that she will have a life worth living. If, however, we genetically
manipulate a healthy embryo by inserting a disability-causing gene, say a gene
causing blindness, then we could be accused of having harmed somebody. We have
caused a particular person, who would otherwise have been able to see, to be
blind. Arguably, such an act is as seriously wrong as it is to blind an infant.
Even if one accepts Savulescu’s principle of procreative beneficence, one might
still hold (what may be termed a “person-affecting” moral principle) that the
degree of moral wrongdoing is greater if we harm some person than if we merely
fail to select for existence the possible child whom we expect would have the
best life.
We also need to bear in mind that what may be an
ethically innocuous choice for a person to make for herself—which career to
pursue, whether to drink alcohol, whether to undergo a cosmetic surgery
procedure—may not be ethically innocuous if a person chooses to impose it on
someone else. That such choices may not be ethically innocuous has partly to do
with our beliefs about personal autonomy and the having the freedom to make
certain choices about one’s own life; but these considerations do not apply in
the case of an embryo, which does not yet have the capacity for autonomy or
free choice. Instead, we can think of such choices in terms of the extent to
which they are likely to improve one’s life, or to be in one’s best interests. A
person can make a choice for himself which is likely to improve his life; but
the same choice, imposed on someone else, may not improve his life, and may
even have a negative effect. This is because some choices, such as the decision
to pursue a career as an investment banker, are desirable for a person only in
the context of their background beliefs, desires, and values, and in the
context of a certain culture. Becoming an investment banker may be desirable
for someone who is interested in banking; who sees a high salary as sufficient
compensation for long, stressful working hours; who values the prestige
associated with rising through the ranks of a successful corporation; and so on.
In the absence of the appropriate context, however, such a choice is not
desirable: not everyone would enjoy a career as an investment banker, and
becoming one would close off certain other, more desirable choices that could
have been made instead.
We should bear this in mind when selecting
traits for our children. Certain traits that we would find beneficial if we had
them ourselves may not be beneficial for our children. In addition, certain
traits that we value today may not be valuable in the cultural context of the
future. Jonathan Glover comments that “John Mackie once said to me that if
human genetic engineering had been available in Victorian times, people might
have designed their children to be patriotic and pious”[50].
Patriotism and piety may have been valued traits in Victorian times, but they
are much less valued today; at least in societies like the
Another source of unease about genetic
intervention are the perceived parallels between current discussions of
enhancement and the coercive eugenics programmes of the last century, and the
idea that enhancement may foster beliefs about some people being fundamentally
inferior to others (this latter concern is sometimes expressed as the concern
that enhancement would undermine human dignity). Advocating enhancement,
however, has no necessary link with coercive eugenics, nor with the belief that
some people are fundamentally inferior to others. To address the concern about
coercive eugenics first, the state-sponsored eugenics programmes of the last
century were objectionable because they harmed people, either by killing them
or by curtailing their freedom to reproduce. Eugenics need not be coercive,
exploitative, or harmful: in
The concern that this sort of enhancement would
undermine human dignity—by which we here mean the basis for the moral status of
human beings[54]—can
take more than one form. On the one hand, Fukuyama, following Silver, worries
that enhancement could undermine the dignity of the unenhanced, since the
enhanced could lay claim to more human rights than the unenhanced on account of
their advanced capacities[55].
On the other hand, Kass worries that enhancement could rob the enhanced of dignity: he comments that
“[t]o turn a man into a cockroach—as we don’t need Kafka to show us—would be
dehumanizing. To try to turn a man into more than a man might be so as well”[56].
We could respond at length to concerns that enhancement raises about the issue
of human dignity (indeed, one of us already has); but in brief, it is helpful
to bear in mind that, whilst having certain traits—for example, rationality and
a capacity for moral action—are often judged to be constitutive of what it is
to be human, our moral status is not generally held to fluctuate with our
capacities in the way that seems to worry some bioconservatives. Various
individuals can possess very different capacities and yet be equal in moral
status. For example, whilst those who are well-educated, athletic, musically
gifted, or witty may have individual capacities that are superior to those who
are uneducated, unfit, musically untalented, or dull, we should not infer that
the moral status, or dignity, of the former group of people is thereby either superior
or inferior to that of the latter. We might even say that the very idea of
humans having equal dignity has its roots in a desire to prevent the stronger,
more intelligent, and more powerful—that is, those with certain superior
capacities—from dominating and exploiting the more vulnerable. Therefore, if we
accept that all human persons who have not benefited from enhancements have the
same moral status, despite their widely varying capacities, it is hard to see
any justification for according a different moral status to enhanced individuals
or for thinking that the existence of enhanced individuals could affect the
moral status of the unenhanced.
In the light of these considerations, we
conclude that there are no compelling reasons to resist the use of genetic
intervention to select the best children. There are, however, important issues
relating to the fact that such intervention would involve the selection of
traits of a person who has no say in the matter, and for this reason it is of
paramount importance to consider at all times the best interests and future
welfare of the resulting children.
Bibliography
Agar, N., Liberal Eugenics: In Defence of Human
Enhancement (
American Psychological Association (http://www.apa.org).
Bostrom, N., “Human Genetic Enhancements: A Transhumanist Perspective”, Journal of Value Enquiry, 37/4 (2003): 493-506 (https://nickbostrom.com/ethics/genetic.pdf).
______ “In Defence of Posthuman
Dignity”, Bioethics, 19/3 (2005):
202-214 (https://nickbostrom.com/ethics/dignity.pdf).
______ “Dignity and
Enhancement”, commissioned for The President’s Council on Bioethics
(forthcoming, 2007) (https://nickbostrom.com/ethics/dignity-enhancement.pdf).
Bostrom, N. and Sandberg, A., “Cognitive Enhancement: Methods, Ethics, Regulatory Challenges”, Science and Engineering Ethics (forthcoming, 2007) (https://nickbostrom.com/cognitive.pdf).
Elliott, R.,
Sahakian, B. J., Matthews, K., Bannerjea, A., Rimmer, J., Robbins, T. W.,
“Effects of Methylphenidate on Spatial Working Memory and Planning in Healthy
Young Adults”, Psychopharmacology
131/2 (1997): 196-206.
Glover, J., What Sort of People Should There Be? (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1984).
______
Choosing Children: The Ethical
Dilemmas of Genetic Intervention (
Godesky, J., “Thesis #25” (2005) (http://anthropik.com/2006/01/thesis-25-civilization-reduces-quality-of-life).
Gottfredson, L. S., “Why G Matters: The Complexity of Everyday Life”, Intelligence, 24/1 (1997): 79-132.
______
“Life, Death, and Intelligence”, Journal
of Cognitive Education and Psychology, 4/1 (2004): 23-46.
Guterman, L.,
“Choosing Eugenics”, The Chronicle of
Higher Education, 2nd May 2003.
Habermas, J., The Future of Human Nature (
Helland,
Human Fertilization and Embryology Authority (http://hfea.gov.uk).
Kaplan, H. et. al., “A Theory of Human Life History Evolution: Diet,
Intelligence, and Longevity”, Evolutionary
Anthropology (2000): 156-185.
Kass, L. R., “Ageless Bodies, Happy
Souls: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Perfection”, The New Atlantis (Spring 2003): 9-28.
Kevles, D.
J., In the Name of Eugenics: Genetics and
the Uses of Human Heredity (
Kramer, P., Listening to Prozac (New York: Penguin, 1993).
Martin, J. A. et. al., “Births: Final Data for 2002”, CDC National Vital Statistics Reports, 52/10 (2003, revised 2004)
Muller, U.,
Steffenhagen, N., et. al., “Effects
of Modafinil on Working Memory Processes in Humans”, Psychopharmacology 177/1-2 (2004): 161-169.
Nordhaus, W.
D., “Irving Fisher and the Contribution of Improved Longevity to Living
Standards”, The American Journal of
Economics and Sociology, 64/1 (2005): 367-392.
Oeppen, J. and Vaupel, J. W.,
“Broken Limits to Life Expectancy”, Science,
296 (2002): 1029-1031.
Owen, D., “Chemically Enhanced”, Financial Times, 10th
February 2006.
Pascual-Leone,
A., Tarazona, F., et. al.,
“Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation and Neuroplasticity”, Neuropsychologica 37/2 (1999): 207-217.
Population Reference Bureau, “2005 World Population Data Sheet” (http://www.prb.org/pdf05/05WorldDataSheet_Eng.pdf).
Quervain, D.
J. F. and Papassotiropoulos, A., “Identification of a Genetic Cluster
Influencing Memory Performance and Hippocampal Activity in Humans”, Proceedings of the
Randall, D. C., Shneerson, J. M., and File, S. E., “Cognitive Effects of Modafinil in Student Volunteers May Depend on IQ”, Pharmacology Biochemistry & Behavior, 82/1 (2005): 133-139.
Salkever, D.
S., “Updated Estimates of Earnings Benefits from Reduced Exposure of Children
to Environmental Lead”, Environmental
Research, 70/1 (1995): 1-6.
Sandel, M. J., “The Case Against
Perfection”, The Atlantic Monthly (April 2004): 1-11.
Savulescu, J., “Sex
Selection—The Case For”, Medical Journal
of
______ “Procreative Beneficence:
Why We Should Select the Best Children”, Bioethics
15/5/6 (2001): 413-426.
Savulescu, J., Foddy, B. and Clayton, M., “Why We Should Allow Performance Enhancing Drugs in Sport”, British Journal of Sports Medicine, 38 (2004): 666-670.
Savulescu, J., and Kahane, G., “Procreative Beneficence and disability: Is there a moral obligation to create children with the best chance of the best life?”, Ethics, forthcoming.
Silver, L.
M., Remaking
Thom, T. et. al., “Heart Disease and Stroke Statistics—2006 Update: a Report from the American Heart Association Statistics Committee and Stroke Statistics Subcommittee”, Circulation (February 14th, 2006).
WADA Athlete
Guide, third edition (http://www.wada-ama.org/rtecontent/document/WADA_Athlete-Guide_ENG.pdf).
Whalley, L.
J. and Deary, I. J., “Longitudinal Cohort Study of Childhood IQ and Survival up
to Age 76”, British Medical Journal,
322/7290 (2001): 819-822.
Williams, B., “The Makropulos Case:
Reflections on the Tedium of Immortality”, in his Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973).
The World Factbook (2006) (https://www.cia.gov/cia/publications/factbook/index.html).
[1] H. Kaplan et. al, “A Theory of Human Life History Evolution: Diet, Intelligence, and Longevity”, Evolutionary Anthropology (2000): 156-185; J. Godesky, “Thesis #25” (2005).
[2] The World Factbook 2006.
[3] J. Oeppen and J. W. Vaupel, “Broken
Limits to Life Expectancy”, Science,
296 (2002): 1029-1031.
[4] T. Thom et. al., “Heart Disease and Stroke Statistics—2006 Update: a Report from the American Heart Association Statistics Committee and Stroke Statistics Subcommittee”, Circulation (February 14th, 2006), p. 4.
[5] Leon Kass, “Ageless Bodies, Happy Souls: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Perfection”, The New Atlantis (Spring 2003): 9-28.
[6] Bernard Williams, “The Makropulos
Case: Reflections on the Tedium of Immortality”, in his Problems of the Self (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973).
[7] Williams, writing in 1973, was
considering a fictional elixir rather than the sort of treatments that some
scientists now see as offering real possibilities for radical life extension in
the foreseeable future.
[8] Or worth extending. For those who do
not believe the distinction between therapy and enhancement to be morally
significant, these amount to the same thing.
[9] John
Harris made this point in the third of his Princeton Lectures, on 16th
March 2006 at the
[10] Population Reference Bureau, “2005 World Population Data Sheet”.
[11] Joyce A. Martin et. al., “Births: Final Data for 2002”, CDC National Vital Statistics Reports, 52/10 (2003, revised 2004),
p. 2.
[12] William Nordhaus, “Irving Fisher and the Contribution of Improved Longevity to Living Standards”, The American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 64/1 (2005): 367-392.
[13] http://www.wada-ama.org/en/dynamic.ch2?pageCategory.id=254#.
[14]
“Chemically Enhanced”, Financial Times, 10th February 2006.
[15] Savulescu, Foddy and Clayton make this point in “Why We Should Allow Performance Enhancing Drugs in Sport”, British Journal of Sports Medicine, 38 (2004): 666-670.
[16] WADA Athlete Guide, third edition,
p. 4.
[17] Savulescu et. al., “Why We Should Allow Performance Enhancing Drugs in
Sport”, p. 666.
[18] Savulescu et. al., “Why We Should Allow Performance Enhancing Drugs in
Sport”, pp. 666-667.
[19] The way in which such categories are defined may be arbitrary to some extent. For example, Savulescu et. al. tell us that “[b]lack Africans do better at short distance events because of biologically superior muscle type and bone structure”, yet athletes are not categorized according to their race. If we are serious about grouping competitors according to biological categories, perhaps we ought to have a separate category for black Africans. That the current way of categorizing sports competitors may not be the ideal one, however, does not undermine the general point that the expected biological potential of competitors is relevant to our evaluation of their achievements.
[20] It might be deemed prudent to permit such drugs on other grounds. For example, if it would be difficult to detect whether an athlete has used a drug, it might be best to permit it so as to avoid rampant cheating.
[21] Michael Sandel, “The Case Against Perfection”, The Atlantic Monthly (April 2004): 1-11, p. 10.
[22] Peter Kramer, Listening to Prozac (New York: Penguin, 1993).
[23] Kass, “Ageless Bodies, Happy Souls”,
p. 22.
[24] For a more in-depth survey of cognitive enhancement and its ethical issues than is given here, see Nick Bostrom and Anders Sandberg, “Cognitive Enhancement: Methods, Ethics, Regulatory Challenges”, Science and Engineering Ethics (forthcoming, 2007).
[25] U. Muller, N. Steffenhagen, et. al., “Effects of Modafinil on Working Memory Processes in Humans”, Psychopharmacology 177/1-2 (2004): 161-169.
[26] R. Elliott, et. al., “Effects of Methylphenidate on Spatial Working Memory and Planning in Healthy Young Adults”, Psychopharmacology 131/2 (1997): 196-206.
[27] Cf. for example, A. Pascual-Leone, F. Tarazona, et. al., “Transcranial Magnetic Stimulation and Neuroplasticity”, Neuropsychologica 37/2 (1999): 207-217.
[28] D. J.
F. Quervain and A. Papassotiropoulos, “Identification of a Genetic Cluster
Influencing Memory Performance and Hippocampal Activity in Humans”, Proceedings of the
[29] I. B. Helland, L. Smith, et. al., “Maternal Supplementation with Very-Long-Chain N-3 Fatty Acids During Pregnancy and Lactation Augments Children’s IQ at 4 Years of Age”, Pediatrics, 111/1 (2003): 39-44.
[30] D. S. Salkever, “Updated Estimates of Earnings Benefits from Reduced Exposure of Children to Environmental Lead”, Environmental Research, 70/1 (1995): 1-6.
[31] L. S. Gottfredson, “Why G Matters: The Complexity of Everyday Life”, Intelligence, 24/1 (1997): 79-132; and “Life, Death, and Intelligence”, Journal of Cognitive Education and Psychology, 4/1 (2004): 23-46.
[32] L. J.
Whalley and
[33] Lee
Silver, Remaking
[34] Cf., for example, D. C. Randall, J. M. Shneerson, and S. E. File, “Cognitive Effects of Modafinil in Student Volunteers May Depend on IQ”, Pharmacology Biochemistry & Behavior, 82/1 (2005): 133-139 and Muller et. al. “Effects of Modafinil on Working Memory Processes in Humans”.
[35] The possibility of truly extreme forms of cognitive enhancement – such as ones involving the creation of vastly superhumanly intelligent machines – does raise special risks and ethical challenges, which we do not discuss in this chapter.
[36] DNA, Channel 4, March 8th 2003.
[37] Julian Savulescu, “Procreative Beneficence: Why We Should Select the Best Children”, Bioethics 15/5/6 (2001): 413-426, p. 419.
[38] American
Psychological Association (http://www.apa.org/monitor/jun01/ritalin.html). We
can also note that ADHD is the most frequently diagnosed psychiatric disorder
of
[39] Julian
Savulescu, “Sex Selection—The Case For”, Medical
Journal of
[40] Sandel, “The Case Against Perfection”, p. 8.
[41] In the
[42] Hundreds of such agencies exist. See, for example, http://www.pacrepro.com/index.htm and http://www.tinytreasuresagency.com.
[43] Many
[44] Jürgen
Habermas, The Future of Human Nature
(
[45] Habermas, The Future of Human Nature, p. 63.
[46] Sandel, “The Case Against Perfection”, p. 5.
[47] Sandel, “The Case Against Perfection”, p. 6.
[48] Nick
Bostrom, “Human Genetic Enhancements: A Transhumanist Perspective”, Journal of Value Enquiry, 37/4 (2003):
493-506; p. 498.
[49] Savulescu, “Procreative Beneficence”. Whilst Savulescu discusses PGD specifically, we can imagine a more general principle that applies to other means of ensuring that one’s children are born with those features likely to give them the best life, such as genetic manipulation of the embryo.
[50]
Jonathan Glover, Choosing Children: The
Ethical Dilemmas of Genetic Intervention (
[51] Lila Guterman, “Choosing Eugenics”, The Chronicle of Higher Education, 2nd May 2003.
[52] Save perhaps for some state-imposed restrictions to prevent parents from severely compromising the best interests of their children in choosing their traits—for example, by choosing to have a child with a disability. Such a choice was made in 2002 by lesbian couple Sharon Duchesneau and Candy McCullough, who used donated sperm from a deaf friend to have a deaf baby. Jonathan Glover discusses the ethical implications of this in chapter 1 of Choosing Children, as do Julian Savulescu and Guy Kahane in “Procreative Beneficence and Disability: Is There a Moral Obligation to Create Children with the Best Chance of the Best Life?”, Ethics, forthcoming.
[53] For a
defence of the right of parents to choose their children’s features, see
Nicholas Agar, Liberal Eugenics: In
Defence of Human Enhancement (
[54] The definition of human dignity as
the basis for moral status is not the only way to explicate the concept of
dignity, but the only one we will consider here. For a more in-depth discussion
of the concept of human dignity in relation to enhancement, see Nick Bostrom,
“In Defence of Posthuman Dignity”, Bioethics,
19/3 (2005): 202-214 and “Dignity and Enhancement”, commissioned for The
President’s Council on Bioethics (2007), forthcoming.
[55] Francis
Fukuyama, Our Posthuman Future (
[56] Kass, “Ageless Bodies, Happy Souls”,
p. 20.